--- title: Exercise --- # Modules Reminder of definitions: For $M$ an abelian group and $R$ a ring, an $R\dash$module structure on $M$ is a choice of a morphism \begin{align*} (\cdot)\in \hom_{\text{set}}(R\cross M, M) \text{ or } \Phi\in \hom_{\text{ring}}(R, M^M) .\end{align*} In the first instance, we think of $\cdot$ as a binary operation $(r, m) \mapsto r\cdot m$ and in the second case, a choice of morphism $r\mapsto \phi_r$. For any group element $m\in M$, we define \begin{align*} \ann(m) \definedas \theset{r\in R \suchthat r\actson_f m = 0_m} \leq R .\end{align*} This is an ideal, because $R$ is an $R\dash$module over itself, so we can define a morphism of $R\dash$modules: \begin{align*} g_m: R &\to M \\ r &\mapsto r\actson_f m .\end{align*} Then clearly $\ann(m) = \ker g_m$, which is a $R\dash$submodule of $R$, which correspond precisely to ideals of $R$. \begin{cases} \end{cases} Proposition : Let $R$ be a ring and $M$ a cyclic $R\dash$module. Then $M \cong R/\ann(M)$ as $R\dash$modules. Proof : **Outline:** - Does the statement make sense categorically? I.e. are both sides actually $R\dash$modules? - Construct an element of $f \in \hom_{R\dash\text{mod}}(R, M)$ - Show that $f$ is surjective and $\ker f = \ann(M)$, finish by 1st isomorphism theorem. Lemma : For any $I\normal R$, the quotient $R/I$ **does** in fact have an $R\dash$module structure. Suppose the Lemma holds. To see that this finishes the proof, let $M$ have an $R\dash$module structure $(\cdot)\in \hom_{\set}(R\cross M, M)$. Since $M$ is cyclic, we can write $M = Rm = \theset{r\cdot m \suchthat r\in R}$ for some group element $m\in M$. > I.e. the $R\dash$orbit of $m$ is transitive. We then define the usual map: \begin{align*} g_m: R &\to M \\ r &\mapsto r\cdot m .\end{align*} - It's clear that this is a morphism of $R\dash$modules: we have $(rx+_Ry)\cdot m = r(x\cdot m) +_M (y\cdot m)$ which just follows because $\cdot$ is a well-defined action. - $g_m$ is surjective: obvious from $M = Rm$. - $\ker g_m = \theset{r\in R \suchthat r\cdot m =0} \definedas \ann(m)$. So $R/\ann(m) = R/\ker g_m \cong M$. *Proof of lemma:* Note that $R$ is an $R\dash$module with action given by $f: R \to \endo(R)$ given by $f(r) = (x\to rx)$ using the ring multiplication. Then we are supplied with a map $\Phi:R \to \endo(R)$ where, say, $m \mapsto (\phi_r: R\to R)$. Let $\pi: R \to R/I$ be the canonical projection. We want to build a map $\Psi: R \to \endo(R/I)$, so fix an $r$ and examine the obvious thing: \begin{align*} \tilde \phi_r: R &\to R/I \\ x &\mapsto \pi\circ\phi_r(x) = \phi_r(x) + I .\end{align*} Note the alternative, i.e. we could try defining this on the quotient directly: \begin{align*} R/I &\to R/I \\ x + I &\mapsto \phi_r(x) + I .\end{align*} but we'd need to check if this was well-defined. We can instead appeal to the universal property: any morphism $f:R\to S$ such that $I\subset \ker f$ factors uniquely through $R/I$. So here we can just take $S = R/I$, and check that $I \subset \ker \tilde\phi_m$. If $i\in I$, then $\tilde\phi_r(i) = \phi_r(i) + I$. Here, we actually need to use the fact that $\phi_r(i) = ri$ and $I$ is an ideal, so $ri \in I$, and this $\phi_r(i) + I = (ri) + I = 0 + I$, which is indeed the zero element of $R/I$. > Note: it's not clear that the analogous theorem "If $R$ is an $M\dash$module then $R/I$ is an $M\dash$module" goes through with this approach!