# Monday February 24th ## Divisible Modules We know that injective implies divisible, and uniquely divisible implies injective. Fact: quotients of divisible modules are divisible Exercise : If $R$ is a domain that is not a field and $M$ is a finitely-generated divisible $R\dash$module, then $M = 0$. Proof (of exercise) : Claim: for any ring $R$, any nonzero f.g. $R\dash$module $M$ has a nonzero cyclic (monogenic) quotient given by modding out by all but one of the generators. Thus if $M$ admits a finitely generated divisible $R\dash$module, it admits a cyclic module. Then $M \cong R/\ann M$, and there are two cases: - $\ann M = 0$, in which case $M\cong R$. Then choosing $r\in R^\bullet\setminus R\units$, then $[r]: R\to R$ is *not* a surjection. - Otherwise, choose $x\in \ann(M) \setminus \theset{0}$. Then $\times x: R \to R$ is the same map as $\times 0: R\to R$, so it is not surjective. Fact: there is a classification of divisible (iff injective) $\ZZ\dash$modules: - $(\QQ, +)$, since the fraction field of any domain is divisible. - $(\QQ/\ZZ, +) = \bigoplus_{\text{primes}} \QQ_p / \ZZ_p$, where $\QQ_p / \ZZ_p = \lim \ZZ/p^n\ZZ$. This is isomorphic to the group of $p$ power roots of unity. On the other hand, $\QQ/\ZZ$ is the group of *all* roots of unity Fact (Classification of Divisible $\ZZ\dash$Modules: : Any divisible $\ZZ\dash$module is isomorphic to a direct sum of copies of - $(\QQ, +)$ - $(\QQ_p/\ZZ_p, +)$ Note that any direct sum of divisible groups is still divisible. Moreover, this decomposition is unique. ## Toward Localization Proposition (Multiplicative Avoidance) : Let $S\subset R$ with $SS \subset S$, $1\in S$, $0\not\in S$. Define $\mci(S) = \theset{I\normal R \suchthat I\intersect S = \emptyset}$. Then 1. $\mci(S) \neq \emptyset$ 2. Every element of $\mci(S)$ is contained in a maximal element of $\mci(S)$. 3. Every maximal element of $\mci(S)$ is prime. Proof : In parts: a. $(0) \in \mci(S)$ by construction. b. Standard Zorn's lemma argument. c. Let $I \in \mci(S)$ be a maximal element, and let $x, y \in R$ such that $xy\in I$ with $x\not\in I$. Then $\generators{x, I} \supsetneq I$, so $S\intersect \generators{x, I} \neq \emptyset$ by maximality. I.e., there exists $s_1 \in S$ such that $s_1 = i_1 + ax$ for some $a\in R$. Continuing this way, if $y\not \in I$, produce an $s_2 = i_2 + by_1$ for some $b\in R$. Since $S$ is multiplicatively closed, $s_1 s_2 \in S$. But we also have $s_1 s_2 = (i_1 + ax)(i_2 + by) \in I$, a contradiction. > See Kaplansky's Commutative Algebra book. Proposition (Prime Ideals Behave Like Primes) : Let $\mfp \in \spec(R)$ and $I_1, \cdots, I_n \normal R$, then if $\mfp \supset \prod I_i$, then $\mfp \supset I_i$ for some $i$. Proof : Suppose $\mfp \supsetneq I_i$ for any $i$, and let $x_i \in I_i \setminus \mfp$. Consider $x \definedas \prod x_i \in \prod I_i \subset \mfp$; then since $\mfp$ is prime, some $x_i \in \mfp$. Corollary: : If $\mfp \supset I^n$, then $\mfp \supset I$. > I.e. prime ideals are radical. ## Radicals Definition (Nilpotent Elements) : An *element* $x\in R$ is *nilpotent* iff $x^n = 0$ for some $n\in \ZZ$. An *ideal* is *nilpotent* iff $I^n = (0)$ for some $n$, and is *nil* iff every element $x\in I$ is nilpotent. Proposition (Nilpotent Implies Nil) : Nilpotent $\implies$ nil. Proof : If $I^n = (0)$, then for any $x\in I$, $x^n \in I^n = (0)$ so $x^n = 0$. Proposition (Nil and FG implies nilpotent) : If $I$ is finitely generated and nil, then $I$ is nilpotent. Proof : Let $I = \generators{x_1, \cdots, x_n}$. Then for each $i$, choose $e_i \in \ZZ$ such that $x_i^{e_i} = 0$. The (check) $I^{\sum e_i} = (0)$. Definition (Nil) : An ideal is nil iff all generators are nilpotent. Corollary: : If $R$ is Noetherian, $I$ is nilpotent iff $I$ is nil. Exercise : Exhibit a ring with an ideal that is nil but not nilpotent. > Need to choose a non-Noetherian ring, e.g. a polynomial ring in infinitely many indeterminates $\theset{t_i}$, and consider $\generators{t_n^n \suchthat n\in \NN}$. Definition (Nilradical) : The *nilradical* of $R$, $\nil(R)$, is the set of all nilpotent elements. Proposition (Universal Property of Nil) : \hfill a. $\nil(R) \normal R$, since $a^n = b^n = 0\implies (xa + yb)^{2n} = 0$. b. $R/\nil(R)$ is reduced, and this quotient map is universal wrt morphism into a reduced ring. I.e., if $R \to S$ with $S$ reduced, there is commutative diagram \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} R \arrow[rr, "f"] \arrow[rdd, "\pi"] & & S \\ & & \\ & R/\nil(R) \arrow[ruu, "\exists \tilde f", dashed] & \end{tikzcd} \end{center} c. $\nil(R) = \intersect_{\text{prime ideal}} \mfp$. Proof (of c) : $\subseteq$: If $x\in \nil(R)$, then $x^n =0$ for some $n$, so $x^n \in \mfp$ and since $\mfp$ is prime, $x\in \mfp$. $\subseteq$: We'll show that if $x$ is not nilpotent, then it avoids some prime ideal. Define $S\definedas \theset{x^n \suchthat n\in\NN}$; since $x$ is not nilpotent, $S$ is multiplicatively closed and does not contain zero, so by a previous result, there is some $\mfp \in \spec(R)$ such that $S\intersect \mfp = \emptyset$. Definition (Radical Ideals) : An ideal $I\normal R$ is *radical* iff for all $x\in R$ there exists an $n$ such that $x^n \in I \implies x\in I$. Proposition (Prime Implies Radical) : Prime ideals are radical. > Idea: the set of radical ideals is much easier to work with than the set of prime ideals.