# Thursday January 16th Recall some definitions: - $\pi\dash$class: $A, B \in \mathcal A \implies AB \in \mathcal A$ - $\lambda\dash$class: 1. $\Omega \in \mathcal A$ 2. $A \supset B \implies A\setminus B \in \mathcal A$ 3. $A_n \nearrow A \implies A \in\mathcal A$. We can define minimal such classes containing any nonempty class $\mathcal E$. **Claim:** A $\lambda\pi\dash$class is a $\sigma\dash$algebra. > Note: this just means that it is both a $\sigma$ and a $\pi$ class. *Proof:* - If $A\in \mathcal A$, then $A^c = \Omega - A \in \mathcal AA$ since $\Omega, A \in \mathcal A$ and $A \subset \Omega$ (uses $\lambda\dash$class properties). - Then $(A \union B)^c = A^c B^c \in \mathcal A$ (using $\pi\dash$class properties). - If $A_n \in \mathcal A$ and $A_n$ are increasing, then $A_n \nearrow A \definedas \union A_n$, which is in $\mathcal A$. Remark: Any $\sigma\dash$algebra is a $\lambda\pi\dash$class. Theorem: If $\mathcal D$ is a $\pi\dash$class, then $\sigma(\mathcal C) = \lambda(\mathcal D)$. > Here we are taking the algebras generated by each, and $\sigma(\mathcal D)$ is the Borel $\sigma\dash$algebra. Since $\lambda(\mathcal D)$ is minimal, $\lambda(\mathcal D) \subset \sigma(\mathcal D)$. Thus it suffices to show $\lambda(\mathcal D)$ is a $\pi\dash$class. > Similar to proof that $\sigma(A) = m(A)$ the monotone algebra. Let $\mathcal G_1 = \theset{ A\suchthat AB \in \lambda(\mathcal D) ~\forall B \in \mathcal{D} }$. Want to show that $AB \in \lambda(\mathcal{D}) \implies AB \in \lambda{\mathcal{D}}$. We can observe that $\mcg_1 \supset \mcd$ since $\mcd$ is a $\pi\dash$class and $\lambda(\mcd) \supset \mcd$, so $\Omega \in \mcg_1$. So choose $A,D \in \mcg_1$ with $A\supset D$. Then $AB, AD \in \lambda(\mcd)$, so $(AB - AD) = A(B-D)$ is in $\lambda(\mcd)$. If $A_n \in \mcd$ with $A_n \nearrow \lim A_n$, then $A_n B \in \lambda(\mcd)$ for all $B \in \mcd$. Then $(\lim A_n)B = \lim (A_n B)$, since both are in $\lambda$. Thus $\mcg_1 \supset \lambda(\mcd)$, and for any $A \in \lambda(\mcd)$, $B\in \mcd$, we have $AB\in \lambda(\mcd)$. Now let $\mcg_2 = \theset{B \suchthat AB \in \lambda(\mcd) ~\forall A \in \lambda(\mcd)}$. By the above result, $\mcg_2 \supset \mcd$. Moreover, $\mcg_2$ is a $\lambda\dash$class, which we need to verify. But then $\mcg_2 \supset \lambda(\mcd)$, then we're done since $B\in\lambda(\mcd) \intersect \mcg_2$ implies that for all $A \in \lambda(\mcd)$, $AB \in \lambda(\mcd)$, which is what we wanted to show. $\qed$ Notation: Let $(\Omega, \mca)$ be a measurable space, then any $A\in \mca$ is a *measurable* set. Letting $(\Omega_1, \mca_1), (\Omega_2, \mca_2)$ be two measurable spaces, then define $\Omega_1 \cross \Omega_2 \definedas \theset{(\omega_1, \omega_2) \suchthat \omega_i \in \Omega_i }$. Then define $\mca_1 \cross \mca_2 = \sigma(A_1\cross A_2 \suchthat A_i\in\mca_i)$. Note that this is a $\pi\dash$class in the case of $\RR^n$: the intersections of rectangles are still rectangles. For $\RR^n$, we define a function $f$ to be measurable iff $f\inv(-\infty, a) = \theset{x\suchthat f(x) < a}$ is Borel-measurable for all $a\in \RR$. Similarly, we say $f$ is measurable here iff $f\inv(A) = \theset{f \suchthat f(x) \in A}$. We thus say $X:\Omega_1 \to \Omega_2$ is measurable iff $X\inv(\mca_2) \subset\mca_1$ where $X\inv(\mca_i) = \theset{X\inv(A) \suchthat A\in\mca_i}$ and $X\inv(A) = \theset{\omega \suchthat X(\omega) \in A}$. Lemma: Given a transformation $X:\Omega_1 \to \Omega_2$ and a class $\mca$ of $\Omega_2$, we have \begin{align*} X\inv( \sigma_{\Omega_1}(\mca) ) = \sigma_{\Omega_1}(X\inv(\mca)) .\end{align*} Proof: We have 1. $X\inv( \sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca) ) \supset X\inv(\mca)$. 2. $X\inv( \sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca) )$ is a $\sigma\dash$algebra. > This follows from the fact that preimages commute with union, intersection, and set difference. So it suffices to show that $X\inv ( \sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca))$ is the minimal $\sigma\dash$algebra containing $X\inv(\mca)$. I.e., we want to show that for all $\sigma\dash$algebras $\mcd \supset X\inv(\mca)$, we have $\mcd \supset X\inv( \sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca_1) )$. Define $\mcg \definedas \theset{ A \suchthat A \subset \Omega_2, X\inv(A) \in \mcd }$, then $\mcg \supset \mca$ and $\mcg$ is also a $\sigma\dash$ algebra. Thus $\mcg \supset \sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca)$, $X\inv(\mcg) \supset X\inv(\sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca))$, thus $\mcd \supset X\inv(\mcg) \supset X\inv(\sigma_{\Omega_2}(\mca))$. $\qed$ > Note: we did not use measurability here. In the case of $\RR$, we had that if $f_1, f_2$ be measurable, then $f_1 \circ f_2$ is measurable. Similarly, if we have \begin{align*} X: \Omega_1 &\to \Omega_2 \\ Y: \Omega_2 &\to \Omega_3 .\end{align*} If we define $Z = Y(X): \Omega_1 \to \Omega_3$, then if $X,Y$ are measurable then $Z$ is measurable. Proof: \begin{align*} Z\inv(\mca_3) &= (Y(X))\inv (\mca_3) \\ &= X\inv (Y\inv (\mca_3)) \\ &\subset X\inv(\mca_2) \\ &\subset \mca_1 .\end{align*} Similarly, if $\theset{f_i}$ are measurable, then the function $F(x) = [f_1(x), f_2(x), \cdotss, f_n(x)]$ is measurable. We can also let $X_i: (\Omega, \mca) \to (\Omega_i, \mca_i)$, then the function $X = (X_1, \cdots, X_n): \Omega \to \prod X_i$ is measurable with respect to the product measure (i.e. $\sigma(\prod A_i)$). Next time: looking at sequences of functions, showing limits are measurable, expected values.