# Ch. XYZ: Galois Theory and Prime Decomposition (April 13) :::{.remark} Two recommended resources: - Samuel, Algebraic Theory of Numbers (Dover) - Matt Baker's [online notes on Algebraic number theory](https://people.math.gatech.edu/~mbaker/pdf/ANTBook.pdf). ::: :::{.remark} Setup: - $L/K$ a Galois extension of number fields. - $P \in \mspec K$ - $Q\in \mspec L$ We saw that $G(L/K)$ acts on the prime ideals above $P$, making all of the $e,f$ values the same, and thus the decomposition into prime ideals in this type of extension is simpler than in a general extension. We'll look at decomposition and inertia groups today. Recall that if $Q$ lies above $P$, then the **decomposition group** $D(Q/P)$ is the set of $\sigma\in G(L/K)$ such that $\sigma(Q) = Q$. Note that $P$ is redundant in this notation, since $Q \intersect \ZZ_K = P$. Also recall that $\FF_Q \da \ZZ_L/Q$ is the residue field associated to $Q$ and $\ZZ_P \da \ZZ_L/P$ and we view $\FF_P \subseteq \FF_Q$. Such an extension of finite fields is always Galois, and the Galois groups turn out to be related to the decomposition groups. For $\sigma \in D(Q/P)$ we defined $\bar\sigma: \FF_Q \to \FF_Q$ where $\alpha \mod Q \mapsto \sigma(\alpha) \mod Q$. It's easy to check this is - Well-defined, precisely by the definition of $D(Q/P)$, - An automorphism of $\FF_Q$: it must be surjective since everything in $\ZZ_L$ is in the image of $\sigma$ since $\sigma$ was an automorphism of $\ZZ_L$ to begin with. But then it's a surjective morphism from a finite field to itself, hence an automorphism. - $\sigma$ fixed $\FF_P$ pointwise Now consider applying $\sigma$ to an element of $\FF_P$, which are of the form $\alpha \mod Q$ where $\alpha$ comes from $\ZZ_K$. But $\sigma$ fixed $\ZZ_K$ pointwise, so $\sigma$ fixed $\FF_P$ pointwise. So each $\sigma\in D(Q/P)$ yields a $\bar\sigma \in G(\FF_Q/\FF_P)$ and we get a group morphism \[ \red_{Q/P}: D(Q/P) &&\to G(\FF_Q/\FF_P) \\ \sigma &\mapsto \bar\sigma .\] The following is the deeper and more important fact about this morphism, which requires a technical proof: ::: :::{.theorem title="?"} $\red_{Q/P}$ is surjective. ::: :::{.proof title="?"} We can assume $\FF_P$ is a proper subfield of $\FF_Q$, since the result follows immediately otherwise. By the primitive element theorem, since $|FF_Q/\FF_P$ is separable we can write $\FF_Q = \FF_P(\bar\alpha)$ where $\alpha\in \ZZ_L$ and $\bar{\wait}$ denotes reducing mod $Q$. Note $\alpha\not\in Q$, since this would mean $\bar\alpha = 0$ and thus $\FF_Q = \FF_P$. On the other hand, we can assume $\alpha\in Q'$ for all other $Q'\neq Q$ above $P$. Why? Sketch: the equation $\FF_Q = \FF_P(\bar\alpha)$ only depends on $\alpha\mod Q$, so if $\alpha$ is not in some $Q'$, just adjust $\alpha$ modulo $Q'$ without affecting its class mod $Q$ to get a new $\alpha$ in $Q'$. So if not, replace $\alpha$ with $\alpha'$ satisfying \[ \alpha' \cong \alpha \mod Q \\ \alpha'\cong 0 \mod Q' && \forall Q'\neq Q \text{ above }P .\] Look at the minimal polynomial $\bar m(x)$ of $\bar\alpha$ over $\FF_P$, some monic polynomial in $\FF_P[x]$, where $\FF_P$ is the reduction mod $P$ of elements in $\ZZ_K$. So we can think of $\bar m(x)$ as some $m(x) \in \ZZ_K[x]$ whose coefficients have been reduced mod $Q$. We'll show that for each root $r$ of $\bar m(x)$ in $\FF_Q$, there is some $\sigma\in D(Q/P)$ such that $\bar\sigma(\bar\alpha) = r$ This is enough, since any automorphism of $\FF_Q$ fixing $\FF_P$ is determined by the image of $\bar\alpha$, which has to go to some other root of $\bar m (x)$. If we can show this statement, this means that $\bar\sigma$ has to hit every automorphism in $G(\FF_Q/\FF_P)$. Define $g(x) = \prod_{\sigma\in G(L/K)} (x- \sigma( \alpha))$. Where does $g$ live? $\alpha$ came from $L$, so $\sigma( \alpha) \in L$, and multiplying over all $\sigma$ puts the coefficients in $K$. Even better, since $\alpha\in \ZZ_L$ is algebraic, this will have $\ZZ_K$ coefficients, so $g\in \ZZ_K[x]$. Now reduce mod $Q$ to get $\bar g(x) \in \FF_P[X]$, and moreover $\bar g(\bar \alpha) = \bar{g(\alpha)} = 0$ in $\FF_Q$, since $g(\alpha) = 0$ by definition since one $\sigma$ in the product is the identity. Thus we know $\bar m(x) \divides \bar g(x)$ in $\FF_P[x]$. Notice that in $\FF_Q[x]$, if we take $g$ and reduce mod $Q$ we get \[ \bar g(x) = \prod_{\sigma \in G(L/K)} (x - \bar{\sigma(\alpha)} ) .\] Since $\bar m(x)$ divides $\bar g(x)$, every root of $\bar m$ has the form $\bar{\sigma( \alpha)}$ for some $\sigma\in G(L/K)$. We want this to be $\bar\sigma(\bar \alpha)$ instead to conclude the proof, so take a root of $\bar m$ in $\FF_Q$ and write it as $\bar{\sigma(\alpha)}$ with $\sigma\in G(L/K)$ :::{.claim} $\sigma \in D(G/P)$ has to be in the decomposition group. ::: If this is true, we're done since $\bar{\sigma( \alpha)} = \bar \sigma (\bar \alpha)$. Suppose toward a contradiction that $\sigma\not\in D(G/P)$, so neither $\sigma$ nor $\sigma\inv$ fixes $Q$, so $\sigma\inv(Q) \neq Q$. By choice of $\alpha$, we have $\alpha \in Q' \da \sigma\inv(Q)$, so $\sigma(\alpha)\in Q$. Then $\bar{\sigma(\alpha)} = 0$, but $0$ is not a root of $\bar m(x)$ since it is irreducible where $\bar m(x) \neq x$ since $[\FF_Q: \FF_P] \geq 2$ and thus $\deg \bar m(x) \geq 2$. ::: :::{.remark} By the first isomorphism theorem, we have \[ G(\FF_Q/\FF_P) \cong D(Q/P) / \ker \red_{Q/P} .\], where we call the kernel the **inertia group**: \[ \ker \red_{Q/P} = I(Q/P) \da \ts{ \sigma \in D(Q/P) \st \bar \sigma = \id_{\FF_Q} } .\] These are the elements $\sigma$ in the decomposition group such that $\sigma(\alpha) \equiv \alpha \mod Q$ for every $\alpha$. Since we have a group action of the Galois group on primes above $P$, we can apply Orbit-Stabilizer: we have $\Stab(Q) = D(Q/P)$ and the orbit is all primes above $P$, so \[ G(L/K) / D(Q/P) \cong \ts{\text{Primes above } P} .\] Taking cardinalities, \[ [L:K] / \# D(Q/P) = g \implies \# D(Q/P) = {[L:K] \over g} = {efg \over g} = ef .\] We also have \[ {ef \over \# I(Q/P)} = \#G(\FF_Q/\FF_P) = [\FF_Q: \FF_P] = f .\] In summary, - $\# D(Q/P) = f$, - $\# I(Q/P) = e$, - If $P$ is unramified, $e=1$ and $I(Q/P)$ is trivial and $\red_{Q/P}$ is an isomorphism. This map is usually an isomorphism, since there are only finitely many $P$ ion $\ZZ_K$ that ramify in $\ZZ_L$. ::: ## Inertia and Decomposition Fields :::{.remark} It will turn out that the fixed fields appearing here have number-theoretic interpretations. ::: :::{.definition title="?"} If $Q$ lies above $P$, then define the **inertia field** corresponding to $Q/P$, written $L^{I(Q/P)}$, and the **decomposition field** $L^{D(Q/P)}$. ::: :::{.remark} Suppose $L/K$ is Galois, and consider an intermediate field $L/M/K$. We can find intermediate primes: \begin{tikzcd} L && Q \\ \\ M && {R = Q \intersect \ZZ_M} \\ \\ K && P \arrow[no head, from=1-1, to=3-1] \arrow[no head, from=3-1, to=5-1] \arrow[no head, from=5-3, to=3-3] \arrow[no head, from=3-3, to=1-3] \end{tikzcd} > [Link to Diagram](https://q.uiver.app/?q=WzAsNixbMCwwLCJMIl0sWzAsMiwiTSJdLFswLDQsIksiXSxbMiw0LCJQIl0sWzIsMiwiUiA9IFEgXFxpbnRlcnNlY3QgXFxaWl9NIl0sWzIsMCwiUSJdLFswLDEsIiIsMCx7InN0eWxlIjp7ImhlYWQiOnsibmFtZSI6Im5vbmUifX19XSxbMSwyLCIiLDAseyJzdHlsZSI6eyJoZWFkIjp7Im5hbWUiOiJub25lIn19fV0sWzMsNCwiIiwwLHsic3R5bGUiOnsiaGVhZCI6eyJuYW1lIjoibm9uZSJ9fX1dLFs0LDUsIiIsMCx7InN0eWxlIjp7ImhlYWQiOnsibmFtZSI6Im5vbmUifX19XV0=) We can consider $e, f$ of $R/P$ in this picture. Going to bigger extensions then $M$ makes $R$ bigger, so $e$ increases as $M$ gets bigger. ::: :::{.theorem title="?"} The inertia field $L^{I(Q/P)}$ is the largest field extension $M$ for which $e(R/P) = 1$. More precisely, \[ e(R/P) = 1 \iff M \subseteq L^{I(Q/P)} .\] ::: :::{.remark} From Galois theory, $L/M$ is also Galois, so the key to proving this theorem involves understanding $D, I$ of $Q/R$. Noting that $G(L/M) \subseteq G(L/K)$, We have \[ D(Q/R) &\da \ts{\sigma\in G(L/M) \st \sigma(Q) = Q} \\ &= \ts{\sigma\in G(L/K) \st \sigma(Q) = Q} \intersect G(L/M) \\ &= D(Q/P) \intersect G(L/M) ,\] so the decomposition groups are related by restriction. Suppose $\sigma \in D(Q/R)$, then $\red_{Q/R}(\alpha)$ is an automorphism of $\FF_Q$. We can also get an automorphism of $\FF_Q$ by taking $\red_{Q/P}(\sigma)$ -- it turns out these are the same automorphism. Why? Both map $\alpha \mod Q$ to $\sigma(\alpha) \mod Q$, which doesn't involve $R$ or $P$. We can thus write \[ I(Q/R) &= \ts{ \sigma \in D(Q/R) \st \bar{\sigma} = \id_{\FF_Q} } \\ &= \ts{ \sigma \in D(Q/P) \intersect G(L/M) \st \bar{\sigma} = \id_{\FF_Q} } \\ &= \ts{ \sigma \in D(Q/P) \st \bar{\sigma} = \id_{\FF_Q} }\intersect G(L/M) \\ &= I(G/P) \intersect G(L/M) .\] ::: :::{.remark title="Upshot"} \[ D(Q/R) &= D)Q/P) \intersect G(L/M) \\ I(Q/R) &= I)Q/P) \intersect G(L/M) \\ .\] ::: :::{.proof title="of theorem"} Let $L/M/K$ with $Q/R/P$, we want to show $e(R/P) = 1 \iff M \subset L^{I(Q/P)}$: \begin{tikzcd} L && Q \\ \\ M && R \\ \\ K && P \arrow[no head, from=5-1, to=3-1] \arrow[no head, from=1-1, to=3-1] \arrow[no head, from=5-3, to=3-3] \arrow[no head, from=3-3, to=1-3] \end{tikzcd} > [Link to Diagram](https://q.uiver.app/?q=WzAsNixbMCwwLCJMIl0sWzAsMiwiTSJdLFswLDQsIksiXSxbMiwwLCJRIl0sWzIsMiwiUiJdLFsyLDQsIlAiXSxbMiwxLCIiLDAseyJzdHlsZSI6eyJoZWFkIjp7Im5hbWUiOiJub25lIn19fV0sWzAsMSwiIiwyLHsic3R5bGUiOnsiaGVhZCI6eyJuYW1lIjoibm9uZSJ9fX1dLFs1LDQsIiIsMix7InN0eWxlIjp7ImhlYWQiOnsibmFtZSI6Im5vbmUifX19XSxbNCwzLCIiLDIseyJzdHlsZSI6eyJoZWFkIjp7Im5hbWUiOiJub25lIn19fV1d) We'll use multiplicativity of $e$ in towers. Recall that $e(R/P) = e(Q/R) e(R/P)$, so $e(R/P) = 1$ iff $e(Q/P) = e(Q/R)$. Interpreting this as the size of inertia, this happens iff $\# I(Q/P) = \# I(Q/R)$, iff $\#I(Q/P) = \#( I(Q/P) \intersect G(L/M) )$. This happens iff $I(Q/P) \subseteq G(L/M)$, iff $M \subseteq L^{I(Q/P)}$. ::: :::{.theorem title="?"} The decomposition field $L^{D(Q/P)}$ is the largest $M$ for which *both* $e(R/P) = f(R/P) =1$. ::: :::{.proof title="?"} Replace $e$ in the previous proof with the product $ef$ and $I$ replaced by $D$, using $\#D =ef$. ::: :::{.remark} Next time: why these theorems are interesting! How ramification and splitting completely behaves in fields vs their Galois closures. :::